Mises Daily

How to Think About Losses

The following is an excerpt from The Stock Market, Credit and Capital Formation, written in German in 1931, appearing in English in 1940, and out of print until last week, when it appeared on Mises.org with the permission of the Machlup estate. This excerpt is from pages 59-68.

While it is perfectly clear that an individual capitalist or speculator may make losses on the stock exchange, it is very doubtful hether “society” can make such losses. We are not, of course, referring here to the losses of one society to another, for instance, to the losses which the inhabitants of any particular country may suffer in respect of investments or stock exchange operations abroad. The question with which we are concerned here is whether an individual’s losses from domestic stock exchange transactions represent a loss to the society to which that individual belongs.

Before we answer this question we must, however, investigate the causes of stock exchange losses.

A holder of shares suffers a loss when the shares depreciate in value: this may be due to (a) damage or destruction of the real capital of the enterprise; (b) a fall in the prospective profits of the enterprise; (c) consumption of the capital of the enterprise; (d) a rise in the rate of interest at which the profits have to be capitalized; (e) a misdirection of investment by the enterprise; (f) a reaction to a previous speculative over-valuation of the shares.

From the standpoint of the “community as a whole” these various causes merit different judgments:

(a) When real capital is damaged or destroyed there is undoubtedly a loss of social capital. The fall in the price of the shares is not, of course, an additional loss; it is simply the way in which the loss to society is expressed on the market.

(b) The fall in the profitability of the enterprise may have various causes. If the demand for the product of the firm declines and the reduced selling price of the product diminishes the firm’s receipts, then the investment of capital in the particular line of production concerned may turn out to be unjustified; in any case the fall in value of the firm’s capital simply represents an adjustment which is expressed by the market in the form of a fall in the price of the shares. The same is true when competing concerns using improved technical methods are able to push down the selling price of the product. The fall in the profits of the firm using the old methods and the reduction in the value of its shares will be more than compensated by the profits of the up-to-date firms and the gain to consumers; thus it cannot be regarded as a loss to society.

Profits may be impaired by a rise in the prices of certain necessary means of production; such a price rise may be caused by a competing demand for these factors by other, more promising types of employment. In this case the fall in profits is not to be regarded as a loss to society. If, however, the decline in profitability is not due to an economic process of adaptation or development, but to some “harmful” interference from outside, then we may say that there is a social loss of which the market takes cognizance through the fall in security prices.

(c) The consumption of a firm’s capital may be due to wrong accounting methods, bad tax laws, or bad business practices, which result in the distribution or taxation of “fictitious” profits. To meet these disbursements the firm either uses up part of the necessary replacement funds (e.g., it makes inadequate allowance for depreciation) or it raises new capital (it waters its share capital or contracts new debts). In these cases the fall in share prices obviously signifies a diminution of social capital.

(d) A rise in the rate of interest must, if the productivity of the enterprise is unaltered, cause a reduction in capital values and consequently a reduction in share prices. If the rise in the interest rate is due to a shortage in the supply of capital, it may be considered disadvantageous from the collective standpoint; if it is due to an increased demand for capital arising out of technical progress, it may be regarded as beneficial from the collective point of view. The fall in share prices does not, therefore, permit the inference that a loss to society is involved.

(e) A misdirection of investment, i.e., the use of money capital for the creation of real capital which yields a return below the marginal productivity of capital in general and is therefore unprofitable, is equally “regrettable” from both the private and the social point of view. Since over-speculation on the stock exchange has sometimes been deemed a cause of misdirection of investment, this point demands special attention.

(f) The losses ensuing from the reaction of the securities market which is bound to occur sooner or later if prices have been driven “too high” by speculation, are what people usually refer to when they speak of “stock exchange losses,” and are the target of their most vehement criticism. These losses, however, are exclusively shifts in the distribution of wealth and of income: they do not in themselves represent any loss to society. This point is not clear even to many trained economists and probably needs to be explained in greater detail.

Although cases (a) to (d), and others of a similar kind, undoubtedly represent losses to the owners of the securities, they are not losses specifically connected with stock market operations, since the cause is in each case on “the commodity side” and the changes in the share prices are merely a reflection of economic events in the sphere of “real goods.” The only relevant cases for our purposes are case (e) which raises the problem of whether security speculation causes misdirection of investment, and (f) which raises the problem of whether security speculation can cause capital to be lost in the actual speculative transactions themselves.

For the moment we will postpone discussing the question of misdirection of money capital; [here] we will try to show that money capital cannot be lost in the transactions connected with security speculation. This is not difficult. It would be much more difficult to explain why many an economist has gone astray on this point. The argument that the money capital which flowed onto the stock exchange might be “held up” for a certain length of time undoubtedly made sense.

The idea that money capital can be lost on the stock exchange seems, however, to make scarcely any sense at all.... [O]ne does not have to be a very good detective in order to reason out that the speculator who sold at a low price lost because he had bought previously at a high price, and to discover, thus, that the money which is being searched for must have gone to the person who sold at a high price, or to use the jargon of the stock exchange, to the person who “got out in time.”

No reader...will, I hope, make the mistake of thinking that nobody or only very few people manage to “get out in time.” There are two parties to every transaction; so to everybody who bought at a high price; there must correspond somebody who sold at this high price, and who then stopped speculating and so was the lucky recipient of the money capital which was believed to have been lost.

Arguments concerning the losses which society is supposed to suffer as a consequence of stock exchange losses usually consist of a confusion of a number of different ideas. Among these are the following: (1) real capital is lost; (2) money capital is lost in the sense that sums of money which would have flowed onto the markets for producers’ or consumers’ goods fail to do so; (3) money capital is lost in the sense that sums of money which would have been available for productive investment are diverted into the channels of consumption and thus flow onto the consumers’ goods market instead of onto the producers’ goods market; (4) money capital is lost in the sense that bank credit which was granted for purposes of speculating on the stock exchange cannot be repaid and thus fails to return to the banks....

Many of these ideas are, however, inconsistent with one another. On the one hand stock exchange losses are accused of having deflationary effects (No. 2), while at the same time it is feared that, as a result of stock exchange losses, bank credits will not be repaid to the banks (No. 4). But what does this last effect imply? It means that the economic system remains more amply provided with circulating media than would have been the case if the credits had returned to the banks.

Let us assume a case of a very heavy stock exchange loss. Suppose that the banks have created credit in order to provide a number of speculators with funds for buying shares which later turn out to be worthless. The unlucky buyers of these shares have transferred their deposits to lucky sellers of the shares, and the” former are therefore unable to repay their debts to the banks. In short, the stock exchange losses in this case prevent the “deflationary” effects which the repayment of credits may possibly have; if they are not repaid, the bank deposits remain in existence, whereas if they are repaid they are, temporarily at least, destroyed.

This (slightly frivolous) manner of reasoning serves to show the danger of carrying arguments to extremes and the need for exercising very great caution in analysing economic problems. If we make the argument even more extreme, we obtain quite different results: if the failure of the speculators to repay their loans caused the banks to get into such difficulties that they had to close down, then the immediate result would be the destruction of all their deposits. In this case the failure to repay bank credits would be more deflationary than their repayment.

In other cases also it can be shown that, theoretically at least, the exact opposite of the expected and feared results is conceivable. Let us take the case of a reduced capital supply due to the consumption of gains made on the stock exchange (No. 3 in the list of interpretations given above). ... The money capital employed to buy shares comes into the hands of the seller, and if he chooses to look upon part of this money capital as profit and uses it for consumption purposes, then the funds available as money capital are reduced in favour of the funds used for consumption.

At first sight it may seem paradoxical to argue that losses on the stock exchange are capable of resulting in an increase of money capital. The conditions necessary for this to take place are, however, not at all unreal. All that is necessary is that the seller should cover his losses out of his income by restricting his consumption.

Let us take the case of an occasional speculator who borrows from his bank to gamble on the stock exchange and buys securities at high prices. The fortunate seller--it may be another speculator or it may be a corporation which has just floated a new issue of shares--receives the full amount of the money capital; the unlucky speculator later sells out at low prices and so receives less from the new buyer of the shares than he himself had paid previously.

If he now makes up the deficit on the debt he owes to his bank by reducing his consumption, thus saving a part of his current income, and if the banks reinvest the repaid amounts, the stock exchange loss will have resulted in real capital formation. As the individual concerned would not otherwise have decided to save, we might call it a case of involuntary saving induced by stock exchange losses. (If, however, the “make-up savings” of the losers are not invested, deflation results. Incidentally, this outcome is the more probable owing to the pessimistic attitude which follows heavy losses.)

Again, short-term savings may be involuntarily converted into long-term savings as the result of losses made on the stock exchange. If A is saving for something that he intends to consume at a later date (such as a long journey or the purchase of an automobile) and invests these savings for the time being in shares, he makes his temporary savings available for the creation of real capital. If, after having bought the shares at 100, he fails to find a buyer who will take them at this price, and finally has to sell them to another saver, B, at 80, then 80% of the money capital invested in the real capital will have been provided out of B’s savings and 20% out of savings which have been involuntarily sacrificed by A. Although A merely wanted to invest his funds temporarily, he was unable to withdraw them from the productive process, and so the loss he suffered on the stock exchange became long-term savings of the economic system.

We have no way of telling how important quantitatively the savings induced by stock exchange losses in practice are. Presumably they are considerably less than the figure for consumption of gains made on the stock exchange. But the principle is significant, that the consumption of savings induced by stock exchange gains does have a counterpart in the formation of savings induced by stock exchange losses.

In the one case the speculator looks upon his gains as an addition to his income and increases his consumption, and in the other case, the speculator considers his losses as a diminution of income and reduces his consumption. In so far, however, as these gains or losses are regarded not as changes in income but as changes in wealth, they represent merely interpersonal shifts in wealth, which may be connected with the valuation of capital but have of themselves nothing to do with the formation or consumption of capital.

 

All Rights Reserved ©
Image Source: commons.wikimedia.org
What is the Mises Institute?

The Mises Institute is a non-profit organization that exists to promote teaching and research in the Austrian School of economics, individual freedom, honest history, and international peace, in the tradition of Ludwig von Mises and Murray N. Rothbard. 

Non-political, non-partisan, and non-PC, we advocate a radical shift in the intellectual climate, away from statism and toward a private property order. We believe that our foundational ideas are of permanent value, and oppose all efforts at compromise, sellout, and amalgamation of these ideas with fashionable political, cultural, and social doctrines inimical to their spirit.

Become a Member
Mises Institute